Recently, I wrote an article named Antithetical Nature of Emotions[efn_note]Antithetical nature of emotions. Niranjan Krishna. (2023, March 13). Retrieved March 21, 2023, from https://niranjankrishna.in/2023/03/13/antithetical-nature-of-emotions/[/efn_note]. Based on the line of argument present in the former, this article presents a quasi-hegelian contention to Utilitarianism.
Related Arguments
1. The Experience Machine
Perhaps the most accessible, although not rigorous, argument is the Experience Machine[efn_note]The Experience Machine. Internet encyclopedia of philosophy. (n.d.). Retrieved March 21, 2023, from https://iep.utm.edu/experience-machine/[/efn_note] by Robert Nozick.
The immediate answer of most people is no. Nozick argues that if pleasure were the only intrinsic value, people would rationally decide to connect themselves to an experience machine. The response contradicts the utilitarian premise.
2. Critique of Act Utilitarianism
The strongest critiques of act utilitarianism aim to show that it approves of actions that are clearly wrong, under the guise of fundamental moral intuitions. Perhaps best portrayed by the Organ Transplant Thought Experiment
Act Utilitarianism would implore us to kill Chucky, maximizing the greatest good of the greatest numbers[efn_note]In classic Spock fashion[/efn_note]. However, as we all agree, hopefully, this nonetheless remains morally wrong.
3. Critique of Rule Utilitarianism
Rule Utilitarianism applies a deontological spin to act utilitarianism. An action is morally justified if it conforms to a justified moral rule; and said moral rule is justified if its inclusion into the set of moral rules would create more utility than other possible rules (including the simpliciter, no rules). In the paper Forms and Limitation, the philosopher David Lyons shows how rule utilitarianism[efn_note]David Lyons, The Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism (Oxford University Press, London, 1965)[/efn_note] is essentially a weaker version of act utilitarianism.
Therefore, subjecting it to the same critiques of Act Utilitarianism; one of which is provided above.
The Premises
Oftentimes, the utility principle is attacked on the grounds of vagueness in its evaluative metric. For using pleasure, or even happiness, leads to easier critiques than the concept of “well-being”. However, the argument presented thereafter will be much stronger, such that the explicit details of the evaluative metric isn’t significant.
Note that goodness and badness are qualities of opposite nature, necessitated by the utilitarian premise.
The Argument
1. Descriptor Lemma
Lemma: A descriptor for all objects in a set of nature \(N\), any criteria that group them in the set, only has meaning if not all objects align with the description prescribed.
Proof.
Assume a descriptor \(d\) for all objects in set \(S\). Then let \(S_{1}\) be all objects in set \(S\) with descriptor \(d\). Here \(S_{1} = S\), implying \(S_{1}\) to be a tautology. Hence, the descriptor \(d\) has no meaning.
2. Contention to the Utility Principle
2A. Goodness and Badness exist in a circular fashion
Proof.
Assume a world without bad acts. Consider the set of all actions \(A\) in the world. Goodness here is a descriptor of acts, in varying degrees, and in this world all acts. Applying the Descriptor Lemma, the descriptor of goodness has no meaning here, as it exists if and only if badness exist along it.
2B. Goodness is measured with respect to Badness, of the greatest degree, and vice-versa
Proof.
Assume the set of all acts \(A\), composed of the set of good acts \(G\) and bad acts \(B\) such that \(G + B = A\). Say goodness and badness are properties with degree such that two acts, \(a_{1}\) and \(a_{2}\), can be compared in order to conclude which is more good. Say all \(g_{i}\ \in G\) are of different degrees, same with the set \(B\).
Sort the set \(G\) in ascending order such that, \(g_{1} < g_{2} < …. < g_{n}\) with respect to degree of goodness, similarly for \(B\) in terms of badness.. Note that \(g_{n}\) is more good when compared to \(g_{n-1}\), which is then subsequently compared to \(g_{n-2}\), all the way to \(g_{1}\) – the least good act in \(G\).
Here \(g_{1}\) is more good than \(b_{1}\) by 2A. Applying a similar line of reasoning as the above, \(b_{1}\) is the least bad act when compared to \(b_{n}\). Then \(g_{n}\), the act constituting the greatest good, is measured with respect to \(b_{n}\), the act constituting the greatest bad. Hence proved.
Therefore, a necessary condition for maximizing goodness is maximizing badness. This introduces a contradiction in the formulation of the Generalized Utility Principle, leaving any possible variants of it incoherent.